What Evolved and Who Made It Happen? Namhee Lee & John H. Schumann UCLA nhlee@ucla.edu This paper will explore two issues. The first is what evolved in language evolution. Most accounts of the evolution of language focus on an explanation for how syntax evolved. But the syntax of spoken language and the syntax of written language (or composed language in general) are quite different. Discourse analysis and conversational analysis has shown that in the syntax of everyday speech, sentences have no pride of place and subordination is actually quite rare. Therefore, if the theory of the evolution of language attempts to account for the complicated syntax, which has been the concern of linguists for the last several decades, it will not be addressing the kind of language that evolved. Complex syntax only seems to appear in composed language -- oral or written. Both these forms of language are created off line with very different psycholinguistic constraints than those involved in spontaneous linguistic interaction. In a sense, composed language is a technology that has allowed us to artificially alter syntax. As such, it is quite like genetically altered strawberries. If one wanted to account for a December strawberry and tried to do so by natural selection one would be hopelessly led astray. Such a strawberry is only possible through mediation by the technologies of genetic engineering. In the same way, complex syntax may be possible only through the mediation of the technologies such as writing that are involved in composed language. Another example would be trying to explain the human ability to see inside the nucleus of the cell. The human eye can do that, but only the through the mediation of the technology provided by an electron microscope. And we would not want to try to explain the evolution of the human visual system by accounting for our current ability to see inside the cell. Therefore, we will argue that what has to be explained in a theory of evolution language is the relatively uncomplicated syntax of ordinary conversation. The second issue involves the role of children in the evolution of language. Here we will draw on arguments from pidgin and creole studies to make the case that children, in general, are no more responsible for the innovations in language evolution than are adults. Bickerton's bioprogram hypothesis accrued to children special abilities to grammaticalize language. But there is substantial evidence that the proffering of innovative grammatical forms is largely done by adult generations, and then the children contribute simply by selecting among these forms those that are easiest for them to learn, produce and understand. The selection process reduces the variation in the adultsĄŻ speech and contributes to the stabilization of the language, but it is not a major source of grammatical innovation. The children, as expert pattern detectors and analyzers of the statistical properties of the input, smooth out the innovations, adapting them to their cognition. We view the evolution of language as the emergence of grammatical structure as a complex adaptive system. Hominids capable of producing words generate strings of words to express more complex meanings. In the interaction among the speakers, certain strings become frequent and then these patterns exist as an attractor state or grammar. In this process, children are simply agents participating in the interaction from which the grammar will emerge. From this perspective, language is not a product of the brain. It is the product of many hominid agents interacting with each other, using many items (words) in order to make meanings. The brain mediates this process in a sense that it produces, comprehends, and learns the forms, but the language itself exists as an invisible and nonmaterial cultural artifact or technology between and among speakers.